Jump to ContentJump to Main Navigation
Structuring MindThe Nature of Attention and how it Shapes Consciousness$

Sebastian Watzl

Print publication date: 2017

Print ISBN-13: 9780199658428

Published to Oxford Scholarship Online: April 2017

DOI: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199658428.001.0001

Show Summary Details
Page of

PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2018. All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: null; date: 20 June 2018

(p.285) Bibliography

(p.285) Bibliography

Source:
Structuring Mind
Author(s):

Sebastian Watzl

Publisher:
Oxford University Press

Bibliography references:

Abrams, J., Barbot, A., and Carrasco, M. (2010). Voluntary attention increases perceived spatial frequency. Attention, Perception, and Psychophysics, 72(6), 1510–21.

Ahles, T. A., Blanchard, E. B., and Leventhal, H. (1983). Cognitive control of pain: Attention to the sensory aspects of the cold pressor stimulus. Cognitive Therapy and Research, 7(2), 159–77.

Allport, A. (1993). Attention and control. Have we been asking the wrong questions? A critical review of twenty-five years. In D. E. Meyer and S. Kornblum (Eds), Attention and performance XIV (pp. 183–218). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Allport, D. A. (1987). Selection for action. In H. Heuer and H. F. Sanders (Eds), Perspectives on perception and action (pp. 395–419). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

Allport, D. A., Antonis, B., and Reynolds, P. (1972). On the division of attention: A disproof of the single channel hypothesis. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 24(2), 225–35.

Allport, D. A., Styles, E. A., and Hsieh, S. (1994). Shifting intentional set: Exploring the dynamic control of tasks. In C. Umilta and M. Moscovitch (Eds), Attention and performance IV (pp. 421–52). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Alston, W. P. (1999). Back to the theory of appearing. Noûs, 33, 181–203.

Alvarez, G. A. and Cavanagh, P. (2005). Independent resources for attentional tracking in the left and right visual hemifields. Psychological Science, 16(8), 637–43.

Alvarez, G. A., Gill, J., and Cavanagh, P. (2012). Anatomical constraints on attentional selection: Hemifield independence is a signature of multifocal spatial selection. Journal of Vision, 12(5), 1–20.

American Psychiatric Association (2013). Neurodevelopmental disorders. In Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders (5th ed.). DOI: 10.1176/appi.books.9780890425596.514988.

Anderson, B. (2011). There is no such thing as attention. Frontiers in Psychology, 2(246), 1–8.

Anderson, B. A. (2013). A value-driven mechanism of attentional selection. Journal of Vision, 13(3), 1–16.

Anderson, B. A., Laurent, P. A., and Yantis, S. (2011). Value-driven attentional capture. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 108(25), 10367–71.

Anderson, C. H., Van Essen, D. C., and Olshausen, B. A. (2005). Directed visual attention and the dynamic control of information flow. In L. Itti, G. Rees, and J. K. Tsotsos (Eds), Neurobiology of attention (pp. 11–17). Burlington, MA: Academic Press.

Anscombe, G. E. M. (2000 [1957]). Intention. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Ansorge, U. and Horstmann, G. (2007). Preemptive control of attentional capture by colour: Evidence from trial-by-trial analyses and orderings of onsets of capture effects in reaction time distributions. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 60(7), 952–75.

Ansorge, U. and Neumann, O. (2005). Intentions determine the effect of invisible metacontrast-masked primes: Evidence for top-down contingencies in a peripheral cueing task. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 31, 762–77.

Ansorge, U., Heumann, M., and Scharlau, I. (2002). Influences of visibility, intentions, and probability in a peripheral cuing task. Consciousness and Cognition, 11, 528–45.

Ansorge, U., Horstmann, G., and Worschech, F. (2010). Attentional capture by masked colour singletons. Vision Research, 50(19), 2015–27.

Anton-Erxleben, K., Henrich, C., and Treue, S. (2007). Attention changes perceived size of moving visual patterns. Journal of Vision, 7(11), 5, 1–9.

(p.286) Anton-Erxleben, K., Abrams, J., and Carrasco, M. (2010). Evaluating comparative and equality judgments in contrast perception: Attention alters appearance. Journal of Vision, 10(11), 6, 1–22.

Anton-Erxleben, K., Abrams, J., and Carrasco, M. (2011). Equality judgments cannot distinguish between attention effects on appearance and criterion: A reply to Schneider (2011). Journal of Vision, 11(13), 1–8.

Arvidson, P. S. (2006). The sphere of attention: Context and margin. Dortrecht: Springer.

Aydede, M. (2013). Pain. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring), Edward N. Zalta (Ed.), <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2013/entries/pain/>.

Aydede, M. and Fulkerson, M. (forthcoming). Reasons and theories of sensory affect. In D. Bain, M. Brady, and J. Corns (Eds), The nature of pain.

Baars, B. (2001). A biocognitive approach to the conscious core of immediate memory. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24, 115–16.

Bach, K. (1994). Emotional disorder and attention. Philosophical Pathology, 51–72.

Bacon, W. F. and Egeth, H. E. (1994). Overriding stimulus-driven attentional capture. Perception and Psychophysics, 55(5), 485–96.

Bain, D. (2011). The imperative view of pain. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 18(9–10), 164–85.

Bain, D. (2013). What makes pains unpleasant? Philosophical Studies, 166(1), 69–89.

Balan, P. F. and Gottlieb, J. (2006). Integration of exogenous input into a dynamic salience map revealed by perturbing attention. Journal of Neuroscience, 26(36), 9239–49.

Baldauf, D. and Desimone, R. (2014). Neural mechanisms of object-based attention. Science, 344(6182), 424–7.

Barnes, W. H. F. (1945). The myth of sense-data. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 45, 89–118.

Barnett, D. (2008). The simplicity intuition and its hidden influence on philosophy of mind. Noûs, 42(2), 308–35.

Baumeister, R. F. and Tierney, J. (2011). Willpower: Rediscovering the greatest human strength. London: Penguin.

Bayne, T. (2008a). The phenomenology of agency. Philosophy Compass, 3, 1–21.

Bayne, T. (2008b). The unity of consciousness and the split-brain syndrome. Journal of Philosophy, 105(6), 277–300.

Bayne, T. (2010a). The unity of consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Bayne, T. (2010b). Agentive experiences as pushmi-pullyu representations. In A. Buckareff, J. Aguilar, and K. Frankish (Eds), New waves in the philosophy of action (pp. 219–36). London: Palgrave Macmillan.

Bayne, T. (2011). The sense of agency. In F. Macpherson, The senses: Classical and contemporary philosophical perspectives (pp. 355–74). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Bayne, T. and Chalmers, D. J. (2003). What is the unity of consciousness? In A. Cleeremans (Ed.), The unity of consciousness (pp. 23–58). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Bayne, T. and Levy, N. (2006). The feeling of doing: Deconstructing the phenomenology of agency. In N. Sebanz and W. Prinz (Eds), Disorders of volition (pp. 49–68). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Bayne, T. and Pacherie, E. (2007). Narrators and comparators: The architecture of agentive self-awareness, Synthese, 159(4), 475–91.

Becker, S. I., Folk, C. L., and Remington, R. W. (2013). Attentional capture does not depend on feature similarity, but on target-nontarget relations. Psychological Science, 24(5), 634–47.

Behrmann, M., Geng, J. J., and Shomstein, S. (2004). Parietal cortex and attention. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 14(2), 212–17.

Bentley, I. (1904). The psychological meaning of clearness, Mind, 13(50), 242–53.

(p.287) Berkeley, G. (1734/2009). Three dialogues between Hylas and Philonous. In D. M. Clarke (Ed.), George Berkeley. Philosophical Writings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Bermúdez, J. L. (1995). Nonconceptual content: From perceptual experience to subpersonal computational states. Mind and Language, 10(4), 333–69.

Billock, G., Koch, C., and Psaltis, D. (2005). Selective attention as an optimal computational strategy. In L. Itti, G. Rees, and J. K. Tsotsos (Eds), Neurobiology of attention (pp. 18–23). Burlington, MA: Academic Presss.

Bisiach, E. and Luzzatti, C. (1978). Unilateral neglect of representational space. Cortex, 14, 129–33.

Bisley, J. W. and Goldberg, M. E. (2003). Neuronal activity in the lateral intraparietal area and spatial attention. Science, 299(5603), 81–6.

Bisley, J. W. and Goldberg, M. E. (2006). Neural correlates of attention and distractibility in the lateral intraparietal area. Journal of Neurophysiology, 95(3), 1696–717.

Bisley, J. W. and Goldberg, M. E. (2010). Attention, intention, and priority in the parietal lobe. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 33, 1–21.

Block, N. (1978). Troubles with functionalism. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 9, 261–325.

Block, N. (1995). On a confusion about a function of consciousness. Brain and Behavioral Sciences, 18(2), 227–47.

Block, N. (2003). Mental paint. In M. Hahn and B. Ramberg (Eds), Reflections and replies: Essays on the philosophy of Tyler Burge (pp. 165–200). Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books.

Block, N. (2005). Review of Alva Noë “Action in Perception.” Journal of Philosophy, 102(5), 259–72.

Block, N. (2007). Consciousness, accessibility, and the mesh between psychology and neuroscience. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 30, 481–548.

Block, N. (2010). Attention and mental paint. Philosophical Issues, 20(1), 23–63.

Block, N. (2011). Perceptual consciousness overflows cognitive access. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 15(12), 567–75.

Block, N. and Stalnaker, R. (1999). Conceptual analysis, dualism, and the explanatory gap. Philosophical Review, 108(1), 1–46.

Boghossian, P. A. and Velleman, J. D. (1989). Color as a secondary quality. Mind, 98, 81–103.

Bonnel, A. M. and Hafter, E. R. (1998). Divided attention between simultaneous auditory and visual signals. Perception and Psychophysics, 60(2), 179–90.

Botvinick, M., Braver, T., Barch, D., Carter, C., and Cohen J. (2001). Conflict monitoring and cognitive control. Psychological Review, 108(3), 624–52.

Botvinick, M. M., Cohen, J. D., and Carter, C. S. (2004). Conflict monitoring and anterior cingulate cortex: An update. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8(12), 539–46.

Brady, M. S. (2010). Virtue, emotion, and attention. Metaphilosophy, 41(1–2), 115–31.

Brady, M. S. (2013). Emotional Insight: The Epistemic Role of Emotional Experience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Bratman, M. (1987). Intentions, Plans, and Practical Reason. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Brefczynski-Lewis, J. A., Datta, R., Lewis, J. W., and DeYoe, E. A. (2009). The topography of visuospatial attention as revealed by a novel visual field mapping technique. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 21(7), 1447–60.

Breitmeyer, B. G. and Öğmen, H. (2006). Visual masking: Time slices through conscious and unconscious vision. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Brentano, F. C. (1973 [1874]). Psychology from an empirical standpoint. Oxford: Routledge.

Brewer, B. (1992). Unilateral neglect and the objectivity of spatial representation. Mind and Language, 7(3), 222–39.

(p.288) Brewer, B. (2004). Realism and the nature of perceptual experience. Philosophical Issues, 14, 61–77.

Brewer, B. (2011). Perception and its objects. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Briggs, R. (2014). Normative theories of rational choice: Expected utility. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall), Edward N. Zalta (Ed.), <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/rationality-normative-utility/>.

Broadbent, D. (1958). Perception and communication. Oxford: Pergamon Press.

Broadbent, D. E. (1971). Decision and stress. Burlington, MA: Academic Press.

Brogaard, B. (2010). Strong representationalism and centered content. Philosophical Studies, 151(3), 373–92.

Brown, R. (2012). The myth of phenomenological overflow. Consciousness and Cognition, 21(2), 599–604.

Bruce, N. and Tsotsos, J. (2009). Spatiotemporal saliency: Towards a hierarchical representation of visual saliency. Attention in Cognitive Systems, 98–111.

Bruya, B. (2010). Effortless attention. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Buehler, D. (2014). Psychological agency: Guidance of visual attention, dissertation, UCLA.

Buekens, F., Maesen, K., and Vanmechelen, X. (2001). Indexicaliteit en dynamische intenties. Algemeen Nederlands Tijdschrift voor Wijsbegeerte, 93, 165–80.

Bundesen, C. (1990). A theory of visual attention. Psychological Review, 97(4), 523–47.

Bundesen, C. and Habekost, T. (2008). Principles of visual attention: Linking mind and brain. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Burge, T. (2010). Origins of objectivity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Buschman,T. J., Siegel, M., Roy, J. E., and Miller, E. K. (2011). Neural substrates of cognitive capacity limitations. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 108(27), 11252–5.

Byrne, A. (2001). Intentionalism defended. Philosophical Review, 110, 199–240.

Campbell, J. (2002). Reference and consciousness. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Carey, S. (2009). The origin of concepts. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Carey, S. and Xu, F. (2001). Infants’ knowledge of objects: Beyond object files and object tracking. Cognition, 80(1), 179–213.

Carpenter, M. and Liebal, K. (2011). Joint attention, communication, and knowing together in infancy. In A. Seemann (Ed.), Joint attention: New developments in psychology, philosophy of mind, and social neuroscience (pp. 159–81). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Carrasco, M. (2009). Attention psychophysical approaches. In T. Bayne, A. Cleeremans, and P. Wilken (Eds), The Oxford companion to consciousness (pp. 78–84). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Carrasco, M. (2011). Visual attention: The past 25 years. Vision research, 51(13), 1484–525.

Carrasco, M. (2014). Spatial attention: Perceptual modulation. In S. Kastner and A. C. Nobre (Eds), The Oxford Handbook of Attention (pp. 183–230). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Carrasco, M., Ling, S., and Read, S. (2004). Attention alters appearance. Nature Neuroscience, 7(3), 308–13.

Carruthers, P. (2009). Action-awareness and the active mind. Philosophical Papers, 38(2), 133–56.

Chabris, C. F. and Simons, D. (2010). The invisible gorilla: And other ways our intuitions deceive us. New York: Broadway Books.

Chalmers, D. J. (1996). The conscious mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Chalmers, D. J. (2003). The content and epistemology of phenomenal belief. In Q. Smith and A. Jokic (Eds), Consciousness: New philosophical perspectives (pp. 220–72). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Chalmers, D. J. (2005). The representational character of experience. In B. Leiter (Ed.), The future for philosophy (pp. 153–81). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

(p.289) Chalmers, D. J. (2006). Perception and the fall from Eden. In T. S. Gendler and J. Hawthorne (Eds), Perceptual Experience (pp. 49–125). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Chalmers, D. J. (2011). Verbal disputes. Philosophical Review, 120(4), 515–66.

Chalmers, D. J. (2012). Constructing the world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Chalmers, D. J. (2013). The contents of consciousness: Reply to Hellie, Peacocke and Siegel. Analysis, 73(2), 345–68.

Chalmers, D. J. and Jackson, F. (2001). Conceptual analysis and reductive explanation. Philosophical Review, 315–60.

Charlow, N. (2014). Logic and semantics for imperatives. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 43(4), 617–64.

Charlton, S. G. and Starkey, N. J. (2011). Driving without awareness: The effects of practice and automaticity on attention and driving. Transportation Research Part F: Traffic Psychology and Behaviour, 14(6), 456–71.

Chatterjee, A. (2002). Neglect: A disorder of spatial attention. In M. d’Esposito (Ed.), Neurological foundations of cognitive neuroscience (pp. 1–26). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Chen, H. and Wyble, B. (2015). The location but not the attributes of visual cues are automatically encoded into working memory. Vision Research, 107, 76–85.

Chen, P. and Mordkoff, J. T. (2007). Contingent capture at a very short SOA: Evidence against rapid disengagement. Visual Cognition, 15(6), 637–46.

Chen, Z. (2012). Object-based attention: A tutorial review. Attention, Perception, and Psychophysics, 74(5), 784–802.

Cherry, E. C. (1953). Some experiments on the recognition of speech, with one and with two ears. Journal of the Acoustical Society of America, 25(5), 975–9.

Chica, A. B. and Christie, J. (2009). Spatial attention does improve temporal discrimination. Attention, Perception, and Psychophysics, 71(2), 273–80.

Chrisman, M. (2012). The normative evaluation of belief and the aspectual classification of belief and knowledge attributions. Journal of Philosophy, 109(10), 588–612.

Chudnoff, E. (2013). Gurwitsch’s phenomenal holism. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 12(3), 559–78.

Chun, M. M., Golomb, J. D., and Turk-Browne, N. B. (2011). A taxonomy of external and internal attention. Annual Review of Psychology, 62, 73–101.

Churchland, P. M. (1981). Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes. Journal of Philosophy, 78(2), 67–90.

Clark, A. (2001). Visual experience and motor action: Are the bonds too tight? Philosophical Review, 110(4), 495–519.

Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the mind: Embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Clark, A. (2013). Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36(3), 181–204.

Cohen, J. (2009). The red and the real. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Cohen, M. A. and Dennett, D. C. (2011). Consciousness cannot be separated from function. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 15(8), 358–64.

Cohen, M. A., Alvarez, G. A., and Nakayama, K. (2011). Natural-scene perception requires attention. Psychological Science, 22(9), 1–8.

Cohen, M. A., Cavanagh, P., Chun, M. M., and Nakayama, K. (2012). The attentional requirements of consciousness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 16(8), 411–17.

Corbetta, M. and Shulman, G. L. (2002). Control of goal-directed and stimulus-driven attention in the brain. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 3(3), 201–15.

Coslett, H. (1997). Neglect in vision and visual imagery: A double dissociation, Brain, 120(7), 1163–71.

(p.290) Coslettt, H. B. and Lie, G. (2008). Simultanagnosoa: When a rose is not red. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 20(1), 36–48.

Cowan, N. (1989). The reality of cross-modal Stroop effects. Perception and Psychophysics, 45(1), 87–8.

Cowan, N. (2001). The magical number 4 in short-term memory: A reconsideration of mental storage capacity. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24, 87–185.

Cowan, N. (2010). The magical mystery four how is working memory capacity limited, and why? Current Directions in Psychological Science, 19(1), 51–7.

Crane, T. (1988). The waterfall illusion. Analysis, 48(3), 142.

Crane, T. (1998). Intentionality as the mark of the mental. In A. O’Hear (Ed.), Contemporary issues in the philosophy of mind (pp. 229–51). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Crane, T. (2001). Elements of mind: An introduction to the philosophy of mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Crane, T. (2009). Intentionalism. In A. Beckermann and B. McLaughlin (Eds), Oxford handbook to the philosophy of mind (pp. 474–93). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Crane, T. (2013). The Objects of Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Crary, J. (2000). Suspensions of perception: Attention, spectacle, and modern culture. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Cristino, F. and Baddeley, R. (2009). The nature of the visual representations involved in eye movements when walking down the street. Visual Cognition, 17(6–7), 880–903.

Crowther, T. (2009). Watching, sight, and the temporal shape of perceptual activity. Philosophical Review, 118(1), 1–27.

Crowther, T. (2010). The agential profile of perceptual experience. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 110(2), 219–42.

Crowther, T. (2011). The matter of events. Review of Metaphysics, 65(1), 3–39.

Csikszentmihaly, M. (1990). Flow: The psychology of optimal experience. New York: Harper and Row.

Cummins, R. C. (1983). The nature of psychological explanation. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Cummins, R. C. (2000). “How does it work” versus “what are the laws?”: Two conceptions of psychological explanation. In F. Keil and R. A. Wilson (Eds), Explanation and Cognition (pp. 117–45). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Dainton, B. F. (2000). Stream of consciousness: Unity and continuity in conscious experience. Oxford: Routledge.

Dainton, B. F. (2010). Phenomenal holism. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 67, 113–39.

Dalton, P. and Lavie, N. (2004). Auditory attentional capture: Effects of singleton distractor sounds. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 30(1), 180–93.

Dasgupta, S. (2013). Absolutism vs comparativism about quantity. Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, 8, 105–49.

Datta, R. and DeYoe, E. A. (2009). I know where you are secretly attending! The topography of human visual attention revealed with fMRI. Vision Research 49(10), 1037–44.

Davenport, T. H. and Beck, J. C. (2002). The attention economy: Understanding the new currency of business. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Business Press.

Davies, M. (2005). Cognitive Science. In F. Jackson and M. Smith (Eds), The Oxford handbook of contemporary philosophy (pp. 358–94). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Davis, L. (1997). Cerebral hemispheres. Philosophical Studies, 87(2), 207–22.

De Brigard, F. (2010). Attention, consciousness, and commonsense. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 17(9–10), 189–201.

De Brigard, F. and Prinz, J. (2010). Attention and consciousness. WIREs Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science, 1(1), 51–9.

De Vignemont, F. and Fourneret, P. (2004). The sense of agency: A philosophical and empirical review of the “Who” system. Consciousness and Cognition, 13(1), 1–19.

(p.291) Della Libera, C. and Chelazzi, L. (2009). Learning to attend and to ignore is a matter of gains and losses. Psychological Science, 20(6), 778–84.

Della Sala, S., Marchetti, C., and Spinnler, H. (1991). Right-sided anarchic (alien) hand: A longitudinal study. Neuropsychologia, 29(11), 1113–27.

Delvenne, J. F. (2005). The capacity of visual short-term memory within and between hemifields. Cognition, 96(3), B79–B88.

Dennett, D. (1969). Content and consciousness. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

Dennett, D. (1993). Consciousness explained. London: Penguin.

Desimone, R. (1998). Visual attention mediated by biased competition in extrastriate visual cortex. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 353(1373), 1245–55.

Desimone, R. and Duncan, J. (1995). Neural mechanisms of selective visual attention. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 18(1), 193–222.

Deutsch, J. A. and Deutsch, D. (1963). Attention: Some theoretical considerations. Psychological Review, 70, 80–90.

Dicey-Jennings, C. D. (2015). Consciousness without attention. Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 1(2), 276–95.

Dorsch, F. (2015). Focused daydreaming and mind-wandering. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 6(4), 791–813.

Doughney, L. (2013). Folk, theory, and feeling: What attention is. PhD dissertation, Melbourne: La Trobe University.

Doya, K., Ishii, S., Pouget, A., and Rao, R. P. N. (Eds) (2007). Bayesian brain: Probabilistic approaches to neural coding. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Dretske, F. (1967). Can events move? Mind, 76, 479–92.

Dretske, F. (1988). Explaining behavior: Reasons in a world of causes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Dretske, F. (1995). Naturalizing the Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Dretske, F. (2003). How do you know you are not a zombie? In Brie Gertler (Ed.), Privileged access: Philosophical accounts of self-knowledge (pp. 1–14). Farnham: Ashgate.

Driver, J. and Baylis, G. C. (1996). Edge-assignment and figure-ground segmentation in short-term visual matching. Cognitive Psychology, 31(3), 248–306.

Driver, J. and Vuilleumier, P. (2001). Perceptual awareness and its loss in unilateral neglect and extinction. Cognition, 79(1–2), 39–88.

Driver, J., Vuilleumier, P., and Husain, M. (2004). Spatial neglect and extinction. In M. S. Gazzaniga (Ed.), The Cognitive Neuroscience (3rd Ed.) (pp. 589–606). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Duncan, J. (1984). Selective attention and the organization of visual information. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 113(4), 501–17.

Duncan, J. (1999). Attention. In R. A. Wilson and F. C. Keil (Eds), The MIT encyclopedia of the cognitive science (pp. 39–41). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Duncan, J. (2006). EPS Mid-Career Award 2004: Brain mechanisms of attention. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 59(1), 2–27.

Ebbinghaus, H. and Meyer, M. F. (1908). Psychology: An elementary textbook. Lexington, MA: DC Heath.

Eccleston, C. and Crombez, G. (1999). Pain demands attention: A cognitive-affective model of the interruptive function of pain. Psychological bulletin, 125(3), 356–66.

Eckstein, M. P. (2011). Visual search: A retrospective. Journal of Vision, 11(5), 14.

Egly, R., Driver, J., and Rafal, R. (1994). Shifting visual attention between objects and locations: Evidence for normal and parietal lesion subjects. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 123, 161–77.

(p.292) Eilan, N. (2006). Sensorimotor skills and perception. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 80, 43–88.

Eimer, M. (2014). The neural basis of attentional control in visual search. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 18(10), 526–35.

Eimer, M., van Velzen, J., and Driver, J. (2002). Cross-modal interactions between audition, touch, and vision in endogenous spatial attention: ERP evidence on preparatory states and sensory modulations. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 14, 254–71.

Engelmann, J. B. and Pessoa, L. (2007). Motivation sharpens exogenous spatial attention. Emotion, 7(3), 668–74.

Engle, R. W. (2002). Working memory capacity as executive attention. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 11(1), 19–23.

Evans, C. O. (1970). The subject of consciousness. Oxford: Routledge.

Eysenck, M. W. and Keane, M. T. (2010). Cognitive psychology: A student’s handbook. Oxford: Psychology Press.

Farennikova, A. (2013). Seeing absence. Philosophical Studies, 166(3), 429–54.

Fechner, G. T. (1889). Elemente der psychophysik (2nd ed.), Vol. 2. Leipzig: Breitkopf and Härtel.

Feldman, H. and Friston, K. (2010). Attention, uncertainty, and free-energy. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 4, 215.

Fernandez-Duque, D. and Johnson, M. L. (2002). Cause and effect theories of attention: The role of conceptual metaphors. Review of General Psychology, 6(2), 153–65.

Field, M., Mogg, K., and Bradley, B. P. (2004a). Eye movements to smoking-related cues: Effects of nicotine deprivation. Psychopharmacology, 173, 116–23.

Field, M., Mogg, K., Zetteler, J., and Bradley, B. P. (2004b). Attentional biases for alcohol cues in heavy and light social drinkers: The roles of initial orienting and maintained attention. Psychopharmacology, 176, 88–93.

Fine, K. (1995). Senses of essence. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong, D. Raffman, and N. Asher (Eds), Modality, morality, and belief: Essays in the honor of Ruth Barcan Marcus (pp. 53–73). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Fine, K. (2001). The question of realism. Philosophers’ Imprint, 1(1), 1–30.

Fine, K. (2008). Coincidence and form. Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 82(1), 101–18.

Firestone, C. and Scholl, B. J. (2014). “Top-down” effects where none should be found the El Greco fallacy in perception research. Psychological Science, 25(1), 38–46.

Flombaum, J. I., Scholl, B. J., and Pylyshyn, Z. W. (2008). Attentional resources in tracking through occlusion: The high-beams effect. Cognition, 107(3), 904–31.

Fodor, J. A. (1974). Special sciences. Synthese, 28(2), 97–115.

Folk, C. L. and Remington, R. (2006). Top-down modulation of preattentive processing: Testing the recovery account of contingent capture. Visual Cognition, 14(4–8), 445–65.

Folk, C. L., Remington, R. W., and Johnston, J. C. (1992). Involuntary covert orienting is contingent on attentional control settings. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 18(4), 1030–40.

Folk, C. L., Remington, R. W., and Johnston, J. C. (1993). Contingent attentional capture: A reply to Yantis. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 19(3), 682–5.

Fougnie, D. (2009). The relationship between attention and working memory. In N. B. Johansen (Ed.), New research on short-term memory (pp. 1–45). New York: Nova Science Publishers.

Foulsham, T. (2014). Eye movements and their functions in everyday tasks. Eye, 29, 196–9.

Foulsham, T. and Underwood, G. (2007). How does the purpose of inspection influence the potency of visual saliency in scene perception? Perception, 36, 1123–38.

(p.293) Foulsham, T., Cheng, J. T., Tracy, J. L., Henrich, J., and Kingstone, A. (2010). Gaze allocation in a dynamic situation: Effects of social status and speaking. Cognition, 117, 319–31.

Franconeri, S. L., Hollingworth, A., and Simons, D. J. (2005). Do new objects capture attention? Psychological Science, 16(4), 275–81.

Frankfurt, H. (1971). Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. Journal of Philosophy, 68(1), 5–20.

Frankfurt, H. (1988 [1978]). The problem of action. Reprinted in: H. Frankfurt, The importance of what we care about. Philosophical essays (pp. 69–79). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Frege, G. (1997 [1923]). The thought. In M. Beaney (Ed.), The Frege reader. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

Fricker, M. (2007). Epistemic injustice: Power and the ethics of knowing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Friesen, C. K. and Kingstone, A. (1998). The eyes have it! Reflexive orienting is triggered by nonpredictive gaze. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review, 5(3), 490–5.

Friesen, C. K., Ristic, J., and Kingstone, A. (2004). Attentional effects of counterpredictive gaze and arrow cues. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 30(2), 319–29.

Friston, K. (2010). The free-energy principle: A unified brain theory? Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 11(2), 127–38.

Fuller, S. and Carrasco, M. (2006). Exogenous attention and color perception: Performance and appearance of saturation and hue. Vision Research, 46, 4032–47.

Gallagher, S. (2007). The natural philosophy of agency. Philosophy Compass, 2(2), 347–57.

Garner, W. R. (1974). The processing of information and structure. Oxford: Psychology Press.

Gertler, B. (2001). Introspecting phenomenal states. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 63(2), 305–28.

Gertler, B. (2007). In defence of mind-body dualism. In J. Feinberg and R. Shafer-Landau (Eds), Reason and responsibility: Readings in some basic problems of philosophy (pp. 285–97). Boston, MA: Cengage Learning.

Gertler, B. (2012). Renewed acquaintance. In D. Smithies and D. Stoljar (Eds), Introspection and consciousness (pp. 93–127). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Ginet, C. (1990). On action. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Gobell, J. and Carrasco, M. (2005). Attention alters the appearance of spatial frequency and gap size. Psychological Science, 16, 644–51.

Godfrey-Smith, P. (1998). Complexity and the function of mind in nature. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Goldberg, M. E., Bisley, J., Powell, K. D., Gottlieb, J., and Kusunoki, M. (2002). The role of the lateral intraparietal area of the monkey in the generation of saccades and visuospatial attention. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 956, 205–15.

Goldie, P. (2002). Emotions, feelings and intentionality. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1(3), 235–54.

Goldman, A. I. (2006). Simulating minds: The philosophy, psychology, and neuroscience of mindreading. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Gollisch, T. and Meister, M. (2010). Eye smarter than scientists believed: Neural computations in circuits of the retina. Neuron, 65(2), 150–64.

Gollwitzer, P. M. (1999). Implementation intentions: Strong effects of simple plans. American Psychologist, 54(7), 493–503.

Gollwitzer, P. M. and Brandstätter, V. (1997). Implementation intentions and effective goal pursuit. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 73(1), 186–99.

(p.294) Golomb, J. D., Kupitz, C. N., and Thiemann, C. T. (2014). The influence of object location on identity: A “spatial congruency bias.” Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 143(6), 2262–78.

Goodale, M. A., Pélisson, D., and Prablanc, C. (1986). Large adjustments in visually guided reaching do not depend on vision of the hand or perception of target displacement. Nature, 320, 748–50.

Gottlieb, J. (2007). From thought to action: The parietal cortex as a bridge between perception, action, and cognition. Neuron, 53(1), 9–16.

Gottlieb, J. P., Kusunoki, M., and Goldberg, M. E. (1998). The representation of visual salience in monkey parietal cortex. Nature, 391(6666), 481–4.

Govorun, O. and Payne, B. K. (2006). Ego-depletion and prejudice: Separating automatic and controlled components. Social Cognition, 24(2), 111–36.

Graham, G., Tienson, J., and Horgan, T. (2003). The phenomenology of first-person agency. In S. Walter and H.-D. Heckmann (Eds), Physicalism and mental causation: The metaphysics of mind and action (pp. 323–40). London: Imprint Academic.

Grassia, M. (unpublished). The puzzle of listening and hearing, unpublished manuscript.

Greene, A. (2013). A pickpocket’s tale. New Yorker, 88(42), January 7, 38–47.

Grice, H. P. (1961). The causal theory of perception. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 35, 121–53.

Gross, C. G. (1999). The fire that comes from the eye. Neuroscientist, 5(1), 58–64.

Grube, E. (2013). The process of experience. PhD dissertation, UT Austin.

Grzankowski, A. (2013). Non-propositional attitudes. Philosophy Compass, 8(12), 1123–37.

Gurwitsch (2009 [1929]). Phenomenology of thematics and of the pure ego. In F. Kersten (Ed.), The collected works of Aron Gurwitsch (1901–1973), Volume II: Studies in phenomenology and psychology (pp. 193–317). New York: Springer.

Gurwitsch, A. (2009 [1979]). The field of consciousness. In R. M. Zaner (Ed.), The collected works of Aron Gurwitsch (1901–1973): Volume III: The field of consciousness. New York: Springer.

Hall, R. J. (2008). If it itches, scratch! Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 86(4), 525–35.

Hamilton, W. (1859). Lectures on metaphysics, Vol. 1. London: William Blackwood and Sons.

Hamilton, W. (1895). Notes and supplementary dissertations. In Works of Thomas Reid (8th ed.) (pp. 741–1034). Edinburgh: Maclachlan and Stewart.

Hansson, S. O. and Grüne-Yanoff, T. (2012). Preferences. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter), Edward N. Zalta (Ed.), <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2012/entries/preferences/>.

Hardcastle, V. G. (1998). The puzzle of attention, the importance of metaphors. Philosophical Psychology, 11(3), 331–51.

Harman, G. (1990). The intrinsic quality of experience. Philosophical Perspectives, 4, 31–52.

Hatfield, G. (1998). Attention in early scientific psychology. In R. D. Wright (Ed.), Visual Attention (pp. 3–25). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Hellie, B. (2005). Noise and perceptual indiscriminability. Mind, 114(455), 481–508.

Hellie, B. (in preparation). The conscious life, book manuscript.

Helmholtz, H. v. (1962 [1867]). Treatise on physiological optics. New York: Dover.

Hickey, C., Chelazzi, L., and Theeuwes, J. (2010). Reward changes salience in human vision via the anterior cingulate. Journal of Neuroscience, 30(33), 11096–103.

Hicks, G. D. (1926). The nature of sensible appearances. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 6, 142–61.

Higginbotham, J., Pianesi, F., and Varzi, A. C. (Eds) (2000). Speaking of events. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

(p.295) Hine, R. (2010). Attention as experience: Through “thick” and “thin.” Journal of Consciousness Studies, 17(9–1), 202–20.

Hinton, J. M. (1973). Experience: An inquiry into some ambiguities. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Hodsoll, S., Viding, E., and Lavie, N. (2011). Attentional capture by irrelevant emotional distractor faces. Emotion, 11, 346–53.

Hohwy, J. (2013). The predictive mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Holcombe, A. and Chen, W. (2012). Exhausting attentional tracking resources with a single fast-moving object. Cognition, 123, 218–28.

Holt, E. B. (1911). Titchener’s psychology. Psychological Bulletin, 8(1), 25–30.

Holton, R. (2009). Willing, wanting, waiting. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Hommel, B., Pratt, J., Colzato, L., and Godijn, R. (2001). Symbolic control of visual attention. Psychological Science, 12(5), 360–5.

Horgan, T. (1993). From supervenience to superdupervenience: Meeting the demands of a material world. Mind, 102(408), 555–86.

Horgan, T. and Kriegel, U. (2007). Phenomenal epistemology: What is consciousness that we may know it so well? Philosophical Issues, 17(1), 123–44.

Hornsby, J. (2000). Personal and sub-personal: A defence of Dennett’s early distinction. Philosophical Explorations, 3(1), 6–24.

Hornsby, J. (2012). Actions and activity. Philosophical Issues, 22(1), 233–45.

Hornsby, J. (2013). Basic activity. Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 87(1), 1–18.

Horowitz, T. S. and Wolfe, J. M. (1998). Visual search has no memory. Nature, 394(6693), 575–7.

Huang, L. (2010). The speed of feature-based attention: Attentional advantage is slow, but selection is fast. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 36(6), 1382–90.

Huang, L., Mo, L., and Li, Y. (2012). Measuring the interrelations among multiple paradigms of visual attention: An individual differences approach. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 38(2), 414–28.

Humberstone, I. L. (1992). Direction of fit. Mind, 101(401), 59–83.

Hume, D. (1999 [1748]). An enquiry concerning human understanding. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Hume, D. (2000 [1739]). A treatise of human nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Hurley, S. (1998). Consciousness in action. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Hurley, S. (2003). Action, the unity of consciousness, and vehicle externalism. In A. Cleeremans (Ed.), The unity of consciousness (pp. 78–91). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Husserl, E. (1983 [1913]). Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy first book: General introduction to a pure phenomenology. Translated by F. Kersten. Leiden: Martinus Nijoff Publishers.

Husserl, E. G. (1991 [1893–1917]). On the phenomenology of the consciousness of internal time. Translated by John Barnett Brough. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

Hyman, I. E., Boss, S. M., Wise, B. M., McKenzie, K. E., and Caggiano, J. M. (2010). Did you see the unicycling clown? Inattentional blindness while walking and talking on a cell phone. Applied Cognitive Psychology, 24(5), 597–607.

Irving, Z. C. (2016). Mind-wandering is unguided attention: Accounting for the “purposeful” wanderer. Philosophical Studies, 173(2), 547–71.

Itti, L. and Baldi, P. (2009). Bayesian surprise attracts human attention. Vision Research, 49(10), 1295–306.

Itti, L. and Koch, C. (2000). A saliency-based search mechanism for overt and covert shifts of visual attention. Vision Research, 40(10–12), 1489–506.

(p.296) Itti, L. and Koch, C. (2001). Computational modelling of visual attention. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 2, 1–10.

Itti, L., Rees, G., and Tsotsos, J. K. (2005). Neurobiology of attention. Burlington, MA: Academic Press.

Jagnow, R. (2012). Representationalism and the perspectival character of perceptual experience. Philosophical Studies, 157(2), 227–49.

James, W. (1981 [1890]). The principles of psychology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

James, W. (1984 [1892]). Psychology: Briefer course. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

James, W. (1987 [1910]). Some problems of philosophy: A beginning of an introduction to philosophy. In W. James, Writings 1902–1910 (pp. 979–1106). New York: Library of America.

Jans, B., Peters, J. C., and De Weerd, P. (2010). Visual spatial attention to multiple locations at once: The jury is still out. Psychological Review, 117(2), 637–82.

Jennings, C. D. (2012). The subject of attention. Synthese, 189(3), 535–54.

Jennings, C. D. (2014). Attention and perceptual organization. Philosophical Studies, 1–14.

Jiang, Y., Costello, P., Fang, F., Huang, M., and He, S. (2006). A gender- and sexual orientation-dependent spatial attentional effect of invisible images. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 103(45), 17048–52.

Johnston, M. (1992). How to speak of the colors. Philosophical Studies, 68, 221–63.

Johnston, M. (2004). The obscure object of hallucination. Philosophical Studies, 103, 113–83.

Johnston, M. (2006). Hylomorphism. Journal of Philosophy, 103, 12, 652–98.

Johnston, M. (2007). Objective mind and the objectivity of our minds. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 75(2), 233–68.

Johnston, W. A. and Dark, V. J. (1986). Selective attention. Annual Review of Psychology, 37, 43–75.

Jonides, J. (1981). Voluntary versus automatic control over the mind’s eye’s movement. Attention and Performance IX, 9, 187–203.

Jovancevic, J., Sullivan, B., and Hayhoe, M. (2006). Control of attention and gaze in complex environments. Journal of Vision, 6, 1431–50.

Jovancevic-Misic, J. and Hayhoe, M. (2009). Adaptive gaze control in natural environments. Journal of Neuroscience, 29(19), 6234–8.

Kahneman, D. (1973). Attention and effort. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall.

Kahneman, D. and Treisman, A. (1984). Changing views of attention and automaticity. In. R. Parasuraman and D. R. Davies (Eds), Varieties of attention (pp. 29–61). Burlington, MA: Academic Press.

Kahneman, D., Treisman, A., and Gibbs, B. J. (1992). The reviewing of object files: Object-specific integration of information. Cognitive Psychology, 24(2), 175–219.

Kant, I. (1998) [1781/1787]. Critique of pure reason, P. Guyer and A. Wood (Eds). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Kanwisher, N. and Driver, J. (1992). Objects, attributes and visual attention: Which, what and where. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 1, 1–5.

Kaplan, S. and Berman, M. G. (2010). Directed attention as a common resource for executive functioning and self-regulation. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 5(1), 43–57.

Kawabata, N. (1986). Attention and depth perception. Perception, 15, 563–72.

Kawahara, J.-I. and Yamada, Y. (2006). Two noncontiguous locations can be attended concurrently: Evidence from the attentional blink. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review, 13, 594–9.

Kayser, C., Petkov, C. I., Lippert, M., and Logothetis, N. K. (2005). Mechanisms for allocating auditory attention: An auditory saliency map. Current Biology, 15(21), 1943–7.

Kentridge, R. W. (2011). Attention without awareness: A brief review. In C. Mole, D. Smithies, and W. Wu (Eds), Attention: Philosophical and psychological essays (pp. 228–46). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

(p.297) Kentridge, R. W. and Heywood, C. A. (2001). Attention and alerting: Cognitive processes spared in blindsight. In B. De Gelder, E. De Haan, and C. A. Heywood (Eds), Out of mind: Varieties of unconscious processes (pp. 163–81). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Kentridge, R. W., Heywood, C. A., and Weiskrantz, L. (1999). Attention without awareness in blindsight. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, 266, 1805–11.

Kentridge, R. W., Nijboer T. C. W., and Heywood, C. A. (2008). What is attended in spatial attention? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 15(4), 105–11.

Kerr, J. S. (1991). Driving without attention mode (DWAM): A formalisation of inattentive states while driving. In A. G. Gale et al. (Eds), Vision in vehicles III (pp. 473–9). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

Killingsworth, M. A. and Gilbert, D. T. (2010). A wandering mind is an unhappy mind. Science, 330(6006), 932.

Kimchi, R. (2009). Perceptual organization and visual attention. Progress in Brain Research, 176, 15–33.

Kingstone, A. (2009). Taking a real look at social attention. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 19(1), 52–6.

Kingstone, A., Smilek, D., Ristic, J., Friesen, C. K., and Eastwood, J. D. (2003). Attention, researchers! It is time to take a look at the real world. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 12(5), 176–80.

Kinsbourne, M. (1970). A model for the mechanism of unilateral neglect of space. Transactions of the American Neurological Association, 95, 143–7.

Kinsbourne, M. (1987). Mechanisms of unilateral neglect. In M. Jeannerod (Ed.), Neurophysiological and neuropsychological aspects of spatial neglect (pp. 69–86). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

Kinsbourne, M. (1993). Orientational bias model of unilateral neglect: Evidence from attentional gradients within hemispace. In J. Marshall and I. Robertson (Eds), Unilateral neglect: Clinical and experimental studies (pp. 63–86). Oxford: Psychology Press.

Kiss, M., Van Velzen, J., and Eimer, M. (2008). The N2pc component and its links to attention shifts and spatially selective visual processing. Psychophysiology, 45(2), 240–9.

Klein, C. (2007). An imperative theory of pain. Journal of Philosophy, 104, 517–32.

Klein, C. (2015). What pain asymbolia really shows. Mind, 124(494), 493–516.

Klein, R. M. and Ivanoff, J. (2008). Inhibition of return. Scholarpedia, 3(10), 3650.

Klinger, E. (1978). Modes of normal conscious flow. In K. S. Pope and J. L Singer (Eds), The stream of consciousness (pp. 225–58). New York: Springer.

Koch, C. and Crick, F. (2001). The zombie within. Nature, 411(6840), 893.

Koch, C. and Tsuchiya, N. (2007). Attention and consciousness: Two distinct brain processes. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 11(1), 16–22.

Koch, C. and Tsuchiya, N. (2008). Response to Mole: Subjects can attend to completely invisible objects. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 12(2), 44–5.

Koch, C. and Ullman, S. (1985). Shifts in selective visual attention: Towards the underlying neural circuitry. Human Neurobiology, 4, 219–27.

Koch, I., Lawo, V., Fels, J., and Vorländer, M. (2011). Switching in the cocktail party: Exploring intentional control of auditory selective attention. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 37(4), 1140–7.

Koene, A. R. and Zhaoping, L. (2007). Feature-specific interactions in salience from combined feature contrasts: Evidence for a bottom-up saliency map in V1. Journal of Vision, 7(7), 6.

Koslicki, K. (2008). The structure of objects. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Kouider, S., De Gardelle, V., Sackur, J., and Dupoux, E. (2010). How rich is consciousness? The partial awareness hypothesis. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 14(7), 301–7.

Kravitz, D. J. and Behrmann, M. (2008). The space of an object: Object attention alters the spatial gradient in the surround. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 34(2), 298–309.

(p.298) Kravitz, D. J. and Behrmann, M. (2011). Space-, object-, and feature-based attention interact to organize visual scenes. Attention, Perception, and Psychophysics, 73(8), 2434–47.

Kriegel, U. (2004). Consciousness and self-consciousness. Monist, 87(2), 182–206.

Kriegel, U. (2009a). Self-representationalism and phenomenology. Philosophical Studies, 143, 357–81.

Kriegel, U. (2009b). Subjective consciousness: A self-representational theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Kriegel, U. (2013). The phenomenal intentionality research program. In U. Kriegel (Ed.), Phenomenal intentionality (pp. 1–26). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Krifka, M. (1998). The origins of telicity. Studies in Linguistics and Philosophy, 70, 197–235.

Kripke, S. A. (1972). Naming and necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Lambert, A. J. (1993). Attentional interaction in the split-brain: Evidence from negative priming. Neuropsychologia, 31(4), 313–24.

Lamme, V. (2003). Why visual attention and awareness are different. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7, 12–18.

Landman, R., Spekreijse, H., and Lamme, V. A. F. (2003). Large capacity storage of integrated objects before change blindness. Vision Research, 43, 149–64.

Langsam, H. (1997). The theory of appearing defended. Philosophical Studies, 87(1), 33–59.

Langton, R. and Lewis, D. (1998). Defining “intrinsic.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 58(2), 333–45.

Langton, S. R., Watt, R. J., and Bruce, V. (2000). Do the eyes have it? Cues to the direction of social attention. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 4(2), 50–9.

Larson, E. and Lee, A. K. (2013). The cortical dynamics underlying effective switching of auditory spatial attention. Neuroimage, 64, 365–70.

Larson, E. and Lee, A. K. (2014). Switching auditory attention using spatial and non-spatial features recruits different cortical networks. Neuroimage, 84, 681–7.

Lavin, D. (2013). Must there be basic action? Noûs, 47(2), 273–301.

Lawo, V., Fels, J., Oberem, J., and Koch, I. (2014). Intentional attention switching in dichotic listening: Exploring the efficiency of nonspatial and spatial selection. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 67, 2010–24.

Le Pelley, M. E., Pearson, D., Griffiths, O., and Beesley, T. (2015). When goals conflict with values: Counterproductive attentional and oculomotor capture by reward-related stimuli. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 144(1), 158–71.

Lee, G. (2009). “Inner time” in consciousness and the passing of time. PhD dissertation, New York University.

Lee, G. (2014). Experiences and their parts. In D. J. Bennett and C. S. Hill (Eds), Sensory Integration and the Unity of Consciousness (pp. 287–321). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Lennie, P. (2003). The cost of cortical computation. Current Biology, 13(6), 493–7.

Levine, J. (2001). Purple haze: The puzzle of consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Levy, J. (1990). Regulation and generation of perception in the asymmetric brain. In C. Trevarthen (Ed.), Brain circuits and functions of the mind: Essays in honour of Roger W. Sperry (pp. 231–48). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Levy, Y. (2013). Intentional action first. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 91(4), 705–18.

Lewis, D. (1970). How to define theoretical terms. Journal of Philosophy, 67(13), 427–46.

Li, F. F., VanRullen, R., Koch, C., and Perona, P. (2002). Rapid natural scene categorization in the near absence of attention. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 99(14), 9596–601.

Li, Z. (2002). A saliency map in primary visual cortex. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 6(1), 9–16.

Lin, J. Y., Hubert-Wallander, B., Murray, S. O., and Boynton, G. M. (2011). Rapid and reflexive feature-based attention. Journal of Vision, 11(12), 12, 1–9.

(p.299) Liu, T., Slotnick, S. D., Serences, J. T., and Yantis, S. (2003). Cortical mechanisms of feature-based attentional control. Cerebral Cortex, 13(12), 1334–43.

Liverence, B. M. and Scholl, B. J. (2011). Selective attention warps spatial representation: Parallel but opposing effects on attended versus inhibited objects. Psychological Science, 22(12), 1600–8.

Lockwood, M. (1989). Mind, brain and the quantum. Oxford: Blackwell.

Luchins, A. S. (1942). Mechanization in problem solving: The effect of Einstellung. Psychological Monographs, 54(6), 1–95.

Lupyan, G. (2015). Cognitive penetrability of perception in the age of prediction: Predictive systems are penetrable systems. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 6(4), 547–69.

Lutz, A., Slagter, H. A., Dunne, J. D., and Davidson, R. J. (2008). Attention regulation and monitoring in meditation. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 12(4), 163–9.

Mack, A. and Clarke, J. (2012). Gist perception requires attention. Visual Cognition, 20(3), 300–27.

Mack, A. and Rock, I. (1998). Inattentional blindness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Macpherson, F. (2006). Ambiguous figures and the content of experience. Noûs, 40(1), 82–117.

Macpherson, F. (2012). Cognitive penetration of colour experience: Rethinking the issue in light of an indirect mechanism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 84(1), 24–62.

Madden, R. (2015). The naive topology of the conscious subject. Noûs, 49(1), 55–70.

Malinowski, P. and Hübner, R. (2001). The effect of familiarity on visual-search performance: Evidence for learned basic features. Perception and Psychophysics, 63(3), 458–63.

Marcel, A. (2003). The sense of agency: Awareness and ownership of action. In J. Roessler and N. Eilan (Eds), Agency and self-awareness (pp. 48–93). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Marshall, J. C. and Halligan, P. W. (1988). Blindsight and insight in visuo-spatial neglect. Nature, 336(6201), 766–7.

Martens, S. and Wyble, B. (2010). The attentional blink: Past, present, and future of a blind spot in perceptual awareness. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 34(6), 947–57.

Martin, M. G. F. (1997). The reality of appearances. In M. Sainsbury (Ed.), Thought and ontology (pp. 81–106). London: FrancoAngeli.

Martin, M. G. F. (2002). The transparency of experience. Mind and Language, 17, 376–425.

Martin, M. G. F. (2006). On being alienated. In T. S. Gendler and J. Hawthorne (Eds), Perceptual experience (pp. 354–410). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Martínez, M. (2011). Imperative content and the painfulness of pain. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 10(1), 67–90.

Martínez, M. and Klein, C. (2016). Pain signals are predominantly imperative. Biology and Philosophy, 31(2), 283–98.

Mason, M. F., Norton, M. I., Van Horn, J. D., Wegner, D. M., Grafton, S. T., and Macrae, C. N. (2007). Wandering minds: The default network and stimulus-independent thought. Science, 315(5810), 393–5.

Masrour, F. (2014). Unity, mereology and connectivity. Analysis, 74(3), 509–20.

Matsuura, A. and Ichikawa, M. (2003). Effects of attention on depth perception of Necker cube. Vision, 15(1), 25–8.

Mattingley, J. B., Davis, G., and Driver, J. (1997). Preattentive filling-in of visual surfaces in parietal extinction. Science, 275(5300), 671–4.

Maudsley, H. (1877). The physiology of mind. New York: Appleton and Company.

Maunsell, J. H. and Treue, S. (2006). Feature-based attention in visual cortex. Trends in Neurosciences, 29(6), 317–22.

Maurin, A. S. (2012). Bradley’s regress. Philosophy Compass, 7(11), 794–807.

McDowell, J. (1994). Mind and world. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

(p.300) Mele, A. R. (1987). Irrationality: An essay on Akrasia. Self-deception, and self-control. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Mellor, D. H. (1981). Real Time. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Memmert, D., Simons, D. J., and Grimme, T. (2009). The relationship between visual attention and expertise in sports. Psychology of Sport and Exercise, 10(1), 146–51.

Mendelovici, A. (2014). Pure intentionalism about moods and emotions. In U. Kriegel (Ed.), Current controversies in philosophy of mind (pp. 135–57). London: Routledge.

Merleau-Ponty, M. (2002) [1962]. The phenomenology of perception. Oxford: Routledge.

Metcalfe, J. and Mischel, W. (1999). A hot/cool-system analysis of delay of gratification: Dynamics of willpower. Psychological Review, 106(1), 3–19.

Michel, J. B., Shen, Y. K., Aiden, A. P., Veres, A., Gray, M. K., Google Books Team, Pickett, J. P., Hoiberg, D., Clancy, D., Norvig, P., Orwant, J., and Pinker, S. (2011). Quantitative analysis of culture using millions of digitized books. Science, 331(6014), 176–82.

Miller, E. K. and Buschman, T. J. (2013). Cortical circuits for the control of attention. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 23, 216–22.

Millikan, R. (1984). Language, thought, and other biological categories: New foundations for realism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Millikan, R. (1996). Pushmi-pullyu representations. In J. Tomberlin (Ed.), Philosophical Perspectives, Vol. 9 (pp. 185–200). Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishing.

Milner, A. D. and Goodale, M. A. (1995). The visual brain in action. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Mine, C. and Saiki, J. (2015). Task-irrelevant stimulus-reward association induces value-driven attentional capture. Attention, Perception, and Psychophysics, 77(6), 1896–907.

Mischel, W. (2014). The marshmallow test: Mastering self-control. New York: Little, Brown and Company.

Mischel, W., Ebbesen, E. B., and Raskoff Zeiss, A. (1972). Cognitive and attentional mechanisms in delay of gratification. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 21(2), 204–18.

Mischel, W., Shoda, Y., and Rodriguez, M. I. (1989). Delay of gratification in children. Science, 244(4907), 933–8.

Mole, C. (2005). Attention is cognitive unison. PhD dissertation, Princeton University.

Mole, C. (2008). Attention and consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 15(4), 86–104.

Mole, C. (2010). Attention is cognitive unison: An essay in philosophical psychology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Mole, C. (2014). Attention to unseen objects. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 21(11–12), 41–56.

Moll, H. and Meltzoff, A. N. (2011). Perspective-taking and its foundation in joint attention. In N. Eilan, H. Lerman, and J. Roessler (Eds), Perception, causation, and objectivity: Issues in philosophy and psychology (pp. 286–304). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Montagna, B., Pestilli, F., and Carrasco, M. (2009). Attention trades off spatial acuity. Vision Research, 49(7), 735–45.

Moor, J. (1982). Split brains and atomic persons. Philosophy of Science, 49(1), 91–106.

Moore, A. W. (1997). Points of view. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Moore, C. M. and Egeth, H. (1997). Perception without attention: Evidence of grouping under conditions of inattention. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 23, 339–52.

Moore, G. E. (1903). The refutation of idealism. Mind, 12, 433–53.

Moore, T. and Fallah, M. (2001). Control of eye movements and spatial attention. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 98, 1273–6.

Morrison, J. (2012). Colour in a physical world: A problem due to visual noise. Mind, 121(482), 333–73.

(p.301) Morrison, J. (2016). Perceptual confidence. Analytic Philosophy, 57(1), 15–48.

Mossel, B. (2005). Action, control and sensations of acting. Philosophical Studies, 124, 129–80.

Most, S. B., Simons, D. J., Scholl, B. J., Jimenez, R., Clifford, E., and Chabris, C. F. (2001). How not to be seen: The contribution of similarity and selective ignoring to sustained inattentional blindness. Psychological Science, 12, 9–17.

Most, S. B., Scholl, B. J., Clifford, E. R., and Simons, D. J. (2005). What you see is what you set: Sustained inattentional blindness and the capture of awareness. Psychological Review, 112(1), 217–42.

Most, S. B., Smith, S. D., Cooter, A. B., Levy, B. N., and Zald, D. H. (2007). The naked truth: Positive, arousing distractors impair rapid target perception. Cognition and Emotion, 21(5), 964–81.

Mourelatos, A. P. D. (1978). Events, processes and states. Linguistics and Philosophy, 2, 415–34.

Müller M. M., Malinowski, P., Gruber, T., and Hillyard, S. A. (2003). Sustained division of the attentional spotlight. Nature, 424(6946), 309–12.

Munneke, J., Hoppenbrouwers, S. S., and Theeuwes, J. (2015). Reward can modulate attentional capture, independent of top-down set. Attention, Perception, and Psychophysics, 77(8), 2540–8.

Nagel, T. (1971). Brain bisection and the unity of consciousness. Synthese, 22(3), 396–413.

Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? Philosophical Review, 83, 435–50.

Nanay, B. (Ed.) (2010). Perceiving the world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

National Institute of Mental Health (2014). Attention deficit hyperactivity disorder, <http://www.nimh.nih.gov/health/publications/attention-deficit-hyperactivity-disorder/index.shtml> (accessed February 10, 2014).

Navalpakkam, V. and Itti, L. (2005). Modeling the influence of task on attention. Vision Research, 45(2), 205–31.

Neisser, U. (1976). Cognition and reality: Principles and implications of cognitive psychology. London: W. H. Freeman.

Nes, A. (2012). Thematic unity in the phenomenology of thinking. Philosophical Quarterly, 62(246), 84–105.

Neumann, O. (1971). Aufmerksamkeit. In J. Ritter (Ed.), Historisches wörterbuch der philosophie (pp. 635–45). Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.

Neumann, O. (1987). Beyond capacity: A functional view of attention. In H. Heuer and A. F. Sanders (Eds), Perspectives on perception and action (pp. 361–94). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

Nickel, B. (2007). Against intentionalism. Philosophical Studies, 136, 279–304.

Nida-Rümelin, M. (2007). Doings and subject causation. Erkenntnis, 67(2), 255–72.

Noë, A. (2004). Action in perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Norman, L. J., Heywood, C. A., and Kentridge, R. W. (2013). Object-based attention without awareness. Psychological science, 24(6), 836–43.

Nummenmaa, L., Hietanen, J. K., Santtila, P., and Hyönä, J. (2012). Gender and visibility of sexual cues influence eye movements while viewing faces and bodies. Archives of sexual behavior, 41(6), 1439–51.

O’Brien, L. (2007). Self-knowing agents. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

O’Connor, T. (2000). Causality, mind, and free will. Noûs, 34(s14), 105–17.

O’Regan, J. K. and Noë, A. (2001). A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24(5), 883–917.

O’Shaughnessy, B. (1981). The will: A dual aspect theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

O’Shaughnessy, B. (2000). Consciousness and the world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Oizumi, M., Albantakis, L., and Tononi, G. (2014). From the phenomenology to the mechanisms of consciousness: Integrated information theory 3.0. PLoS Computational Biology, 10(5), e1003588.

(p.302) Oken, B. S., Salinsky, M. C., and Elsas, S. M. (2006). Vigilance, alertness, or sustained attention: Physiological basis and measurement. Clinical Neurophysiology, 117(9), 1885–901.

Orlandi, N. (2011). Ambiguous figures and representationalism. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 10(3), 307–23.

Pacherie, E. (2006). Toward a dynamic theory of intentions. In S. Pockett, W. P. Banks, and S. Gallagher (Eds), Does consciousness cause behavior? (pp. 145–67). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Pacherie, E. (2008). The phenomenology of action: A conceptual framework. Cognition, 107(1), 179–217.

Pacherie, E. (2010). Self-agency. In S. Gallagher (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of the self (pp. 442–64). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Parasuraman, R. (Ed.) (2000). The attentive brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Parasuraman, R., Warm, J. S., and See, J. E. (2000). Brain systems of vigilance. In R. Parasuraman (Ed.), The attentive brain (pp. 221–56). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Parfit, D. (1971). Personal identity. Philosophical Review, 80(1), 3–27.

Pashler, H. (1998). The psychology of attention. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Pashler, H., Luck, S. J., Hillyard, S. A., Mangun, G. R., O’Brien, S., and Gazzaniga, M. S. (1994). Sequential operation of disconnected cerebral hemispheres in split-brain patients. NeuroReport, 5(17), 2381–4.

Paul, L. A. (2002). Logical parts. Noûs, 36(4), 578–96.

Pautz, A. (2007). Intentionalism and perceptual presence. Philosophical Perspectives, 21(1), 495–541.

Pautz, A. (2008). The interdependence of phenomenology and intentionality. Monist, 91(2), 250–72.

Pautz, A. (2010). Why explain visual experience in terms of content? In B. Nanay (Ed.), Perceiving the World (pp. 442–64). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Pautz, A. (2011). Can disjunctivists explain our access to the sensible world? Philosophical Issues, 21(1), 384–433.

Peacocke, C. (1983). Sense and content: Experience, thought, and their relations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Peacocke, C. (2000). Conscious attitudes, attention, and self-knowledge. In C. Wright, B. Smith, and C. Macdonald (Eds), Knowing our own minds (pp. 63–98). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Peacocke, C. (2007). Mental action and self-awareness I. In J. Cohen and B. McLaughlin (Eds), Contemporary debates in the philosophy of mind (pp. 358–76). Oxford: Blackwell.

Peacocke, C. (2008a). Mental action and self-awareness II. Epistemology. In L. O’Brien and M. Soteriou (Eds), Mental action (pp. 192–214). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Peacocke, C. (2008b). Sensational properties: Theses to accept and theses to reject. Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 62, 7–24.

Peacocke, C. (2014). The mirror of the world: Subjects, consciousness, and self-consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Petersen, S. E. and Posner, M. I. (2012). The attention system of the human brain: 20 years after. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 35, 73–89.

Phillips, I. (2011). Indiscriminability and experience of change. Philosophical Quarterly, 61(245), 808–27.

Phillips, I. (2014). Experience of and in time. Philosophy Compass, 9(2), 131–44.

Pianesi, F. and Varzi, A. (1996). Events, topology, and temporal relations. Monist, 78(1), 89–116.

Pisella, L., Arzi, M., and Rossetti, Y. (1998). The timing of color and location processing in the motor context. Experimental Brain Research, 121, 270–6.

(p.303) Pitt, D. (2004). The phenomenology of cognition, or, what is it like to think that p? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 69(1), 1–36.

Platts, M. (1979). Ways of meaning: An introduction to a philosophy of language. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

Polanczyk, G., de Lima, M. S., Horta, B. L., et al. (2007). The worldwide prevalence of ADHD: A systematic review and metaregression analysis. American Journal of Psychiatry, 164(6), 942–8.

Polger, T. W. (2007). Realization and the metaphysics of mind. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 85(2), 233–59.

Portner, P. (2004). The semantics of imperatives within a theory of clause types. Semantics and Linguistic Theory, 14, 235–52.

Portner, P. (2007). Imperatives and modals. Natural Language Semantics, 15(4), 351–83.

Posner, M. I. (1980). Orienting of attention. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 32(1), 3–25.

Posner, M. I. (Ed.) (2011). Cognitive neuroscience of attention. New York: Guilford Press.

Posner, M. I. and Cohen, Y. (1984). Components of visual orienting. Attention and Performance X: Control of Language Processes, 32, 531–56.

Posner, M. I. and Petersen, S. E. (1989). The attention system of the human brain. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 13, 25–42.

Prettyman, A. (2013). Attention and conscious perception. PhD dissertation, University of Toronto.

Prinz, J. (2005). A neurofunctional theory of consciousness. In A. Brook and K. Akins (Eds), Cognition and the brain: The philosophy and neuroscience movement (pp. 381–96). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Prinz, J. (2011). Is attention necessary and sufficient for consciousness? In C. Mole, D. Smithies, and W. Wu (Eds), Attention: Philosophical and psychological essays (pp. 174–203). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Prinz, J. J. (2012). The conscious brain: How attention engenders experience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Puccetti, R. (1981). The case for mental duality: Evidence from split-brain data and other considerations. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 4(1), 93–123.

Pylyshyn, Z. W. (2001). Visual indexes, preconceptual objects, and situated vision. Cognition, 80, 127–58.

Quinlan, P. T. (2003). Visual feature integration theory: Past, present, and future. Psychological Bulletin, 129(5), 643–73.

Rainville, P., Carrier, B., Hofbauer, R., Bushnell, M., and Duncan, G. (1999). Dissociation of sensory and affective dimensions of pain using hypnotic modulation. Pain, 82(2), 159–71.

Rao, R. P. and Ballard, D. H. (1999). Predictive coding in the visual cortex: A functional interpretation of some extra-classical receptive-field effects. Nature Neuroscience, 2(1), 79–87.

Rayo, A. (2013). The construction of logical space. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Reddy, L., Wilken, P., and Koch, C. (2004). Face-gender discrimination is possible in the near-absence of attention. Journal of Vision, 4(2), 4.

Reddy, L., Reddy, L., and Koch, C. (2006). Face identification in the near-absence of focal attention. Vision Research, 46(15), 2336–43.

Reddy, V. (2008). How infants know minds. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Reid, T. (2000 [1872]). The works of Thomas Reid, New York: Elibron Classics.

Rescorla, M. (2015). Bayesian Perceptual Psychology. In M. Matthen (Ed.), The Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of Perception (pp. 694–716). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Ribot, T. H. (1889). Psychologie de l’attention. Paris: Librairie Félix Alcan. Translated as The psychology of attention. Chicago, IL: Open Court Publishing, 1890.

(p.304) Ristic, J., Friesen, C. K., and Kingstone, A. (2002). Are eyes special? It depends on how you look at it. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review, 9(3), 507–13.

Roelofs, A. (2005). The visual-auditory color-word Stroop asymmetry and its time course. Memory and Cognition, 33, 1325–36.

Roessler, J. (2000). Attention and the self. An appreciation of C. O. Evans’ “The Subject of Consciousness.” Journal of Consciousness Studies, 7(5), 76–82.

Roessler, J. and Eilan, N. (Eds) (2003). Agency and self-awareness: Issues in philosophy and psychology. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Rolke, B., Dinkelbach, A., Hein, E., and Ulrich, R. (2008). Does attention impair temporal discrimination? Examining non-attentional accounts. Psychological Research, 72(1), 49–60.

Rooth, M. (1992). A theory of focus interpretation. Natural Language Semantics, 1(1), 75–116.

Rothstein, S. D. (2004). Structuring events: A study in the semantics of lexical aspect. Oxford: Blackwell.

Rowe, W. L. (1991). Thomas Reid on freedom and morality. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

Rubinstein, J. S., Meyer, D. E., and Evans, J. E. (2001). Executive control of cognitive processes in task switching. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 27(4), 763.

Ruthruff, E., Pashler, H. E., and Klaassen, A. (2001). Processing bottlenecks in dual-task performance: Structural limitation or strategic postponement? Psychonomic Bulletin and Review, 8(1), 73–80.

Saenz, M., Buracas, G. T., and Boynton, G. M. (2002). Global effects of feature-based attention in human visual cortex. Nature Neuroscience, 5(7), 631–2.

Salvucci, D. D. and Taatgen, N. A. (2008). Threaded cognition: An integrated theory of concurrent multitasking. Psychological Review, 115(1), 101.

Sanford, D. H. (2011). Determinates vs. Determinables. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring), Edward N. Zalta (Ed.), <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2011/entries/determinate-determinables/>.

Sartre, J. P. (1992 [1943]). Being and nothingness. Translated by Hazel E. Barnes. New York: Washington Square Press.

Scanlon, T. (1998). What we owe to each other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Schaffer, J. (2010a). The internal relatedness of all things. Mind, 119(474), 341–76.

Schaffer, J. (2010b). Monism: The priority of the whole. Philosophical Review, 119(1), 31–76.

Scharlau, I. (2002). Leading, but not trailing, primes influence temporal order perception: Further evidence for an attentional account of perceptual latency priming. Perception and Psychophysics, 64, 1346–60.

Scharlau, I. and Ansorge, U. (2003). Direct parameter specification of an attention shift: Evidence from perceptual latency priming. Vision Research, 43, 1351–63.

Scharlau, I. and Horstmann, G. (2006). Perceptual latency priming and illusory line motion: Facilitation by gradients of attention? Advances in Cognitive Psychology, 2, 87–97.

Scharlau, I. and Neumann, O. (2003). Perceptual latency priming by masked and unmasked stimuli: Evidence for an attentional interpretation. Psychological Research/Psychologische Forschung, 67, 184–96.

Schechter, E. (2012). The switch model of split-brain consciousness. Philosophical Psychology, 25(2), 203–26.

Schechter, E. (2013). The unity of consciousness: Subjects and objectivity. Philosophical Studies, 165(2), 671–92.

Schechter, E. (2015). The subject in neuropsychology: Individuating minds in the split-brain case. Mind and Language, 30(5), 501–25.

Schellenberg, S. (2008). The situation-dependency of perception. Journal of Philosophy, 150(2), 55–84.

(p.305) Schellenberg, S. (2011). Perceptual Content Defended. Noûs, 45(4), 714–50.

Schellenberg, S. (2016). Perceptual particularity. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 93(1), 25–54.

Schmidt, L. J., Belopolsky, A. V., and Theeuwes, J. (2015). Potential threat attracts attention and interferes with voluntary saccades. Emotion, 15(3), 329–38.

Schneider, K. A. (2006). Does attention alter appearance? Perception and Psychophysics, 68, 800–14.

Schneider, K. A. (2011). Attention alters decision criteria but not appearance: A reanalysis of Anton-Erxleben, Abrams, and Carrasco (2010). Journal of Vision, 11(13), 7, 1–8.

Schneider, K. A., and Komlos, M. (2008). Attention biases decisions but does not alter appearance. Journal of Vision, 8(15), 3, 1–10.

Scholl, B. (2001). Objects and attention: The state of the art. Cognition, 80, 1–46.

Scholl, B. and Pylyshyn, Z. (1999). Tracking multiple items through occlusion: Clues to visual objecthood. Cognitive Psychology, 38, 259–90.

Schooler, J. W., Smallwood, J., Christoff, K., Handy, T. C., Reichle, E. D., and Sayette, M. A. (2011). Meta-awareness, perceptual decoupling and the wandering mind. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 15(7), 319–26.

Schroeder, T. (2014). Desire. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/desire/>.

Schumacher, E. H., Seymour, T. L., Glass, J. M., Fencsik, D. E., Lauber, E. J., Kieras, D. E., and Meyer, D. E. (2001). Virtually perfect time sharing in dual-task performance: Uncorking the central cognitive bottleneck. Psychological Science, 12(2), 101–8.

Schwitzgebel, E. (2008). The unreliability of naive introspection. Philosophical Review, 117(2), 245–73.

Schwitzgebel, E. (2010). What’s in people’s stream of experience during philosophy talks? http://schwitzsplinters.blogspot.com/ (accessed April 9, 2010).

Searle, J. R. (1969). Speech acts: An essay in the philosophy of language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Searle, J. R. (1983). Intentionality: An essay in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Searle, J. R. (2000). Consciousness. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 23, 557–78.

Serences, J. T. and Kastner, S. (2014). A multi-level account of selective attention. In A. C. Nobre and S. Kastner, The Oxford handbook of attention (pp. 76–104). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Serences, J. T., Shomstein, S., Leber, A. B., Golay, X., Egeth, H. E., and Yantis, S. (2005). Coordination of voluntary and stimulus-driven attentional control in human cortex. Psychological Science, 16(2), 114–22.

Shea, N. (2013). Naturalising representational content. Philosophy Compass, 8(5), 496–509.

Shimada, H. (1990). Effect of auditory presentation of words on color naming: The intermodal Stroop effect. Perceptual and Motor Skills, 70, 1155–61.

Shiu, L.-P. and Pashler, H. (1995). Spatial attention and vernier acuity. Vision Research, 35, 337–43.

Shoemaker, S. (1981). Some varieties of functionalism. Philosophical Topics, 12(1), 93–119.

Shoemaker, S. (1994). Phenomenal character. Noûs, 28, 21–38.

Shoemaker, S. (1996). The first-person perspective and other essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Shoemaker, S. (2006). On the way things appear. In J. Hawthorne and T. Gendler (Eds), Perceptual experience (pp. 461–80). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Shoemaker, S. (2007). Physical Realization. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Shomstein, S. and Yantis, S. (2004). Control of attention shifts between vision and audition in human cortex. Journal of Neuroscience, 24(47), 10702–6.

(p.306) Siegel, S. (2010). The contents of visual experience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Siegel, S. (2013). Are there Edenic grounds of perceptual intentionality? Analysis, 73(2), 329–44.

Siegel, S. (2014). Affordances and the contents of perception. In B. Brogaard (Ed.), Does perception have content? (pp. 51–74). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Siewert, C. (2004). Is experience transparent? Philosophical Studies, 117(1), 15–41.

Siewert, C. (2013). Intellectualism, experience, and motor-understanding. In J. Schear (Ed.), Mind, reason, and being-in-the-world: The McDowell/Dreyfus debate (pp. 197–225). Oxford: Routledge.

Simon, V., Czobor, P., Bálint, S., Mészáros, Á., and Bitter, I. (2009). Prevalence and correlates of adult attention-deficit hyperactivity disorder: Meta-analysis. British Journal of Psychiatry, 194(3), 204–11.

Simons, D. J. (2000). Attentional capture and inattentional blindness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 4, 147–55.

Simons, D. J. and Chabris, C. F. (1999). Gorillas in our midst: Sustained inattentional blindness for dynamic events. Perception, 28, 1059–74.

Simons, D. and Chabris, C. F. (2010). The invisible gorilla: And other ways our intuitions deceive us. New York: Crown.

Simons, D. J. and Levin, D. T. (1998). Failure to detect changes to people during a real-world interaction. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review, 5(4), 644–9.

Simons, P. (1987). Parts: A study in ontology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Sligte, I. G., Scholte, H. S., and Lamme, V. A. (2008). Are there multiple visual short-term memory stores? PLOS One, 3(2), e1699.

Smallwood, J. and Schooler, J. W. (2006). The restless mind. Psychological Bulletin, 132(6), 946.

Smallwood, J., Brown, K., Baird, B., and Schooler, J. W. (2012). Cooperation between the default mode network and the frontal-parietal network in the production of an internal train of thought. Brain Research, 1428, 60–70.

Smith, B. (1988). The soul and its parts: A study in Aristotle and Brentano. Brentano Studien, 1, 75–88.

Smith, D. T. and Schenk, T. (2012). The premotor theory of attention: Time to move on? Neuropsychologia, 50(6), 1104–14.

Smithies, D. (2011). Attention is rational-access consciousness. In C. Mole, D. Smithies, and W. Wu (Eds), Attention: Philosophical and psychological essays (pp. 247–73). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Smithies, D. (2012). A simple theory of introspection. In D. Smithies and D. Stoljar (Eds), Introspection and consciousness (pp. 259–94). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Smithies, D. and Stoljar, D. (Eds) (2012). Introspection and consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Snowdon, P. (1990). The objects of perceptual experience. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 64, 121–50.

Solomon, R. C. (1993). The passions: Emotions and the meaning of life. Cambridge, MA: Hackett Publishing.

Soteriou, M. (2013). The mind’s construction: The ontology of mind and mental action. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Speaks, J. (2010). Attention and intentionalism. Philosophical Quarterly, 60(239), 325–42.

Spence, C. J. and Driver, J. (1994). Covert spatial orienting in audition: Exogenous and endogenous mechanisms. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 20(3), 555–74.

Spence, C. and Santangelo, V. (2009). Capturing spatial attention with multisensory cues: A review. Hearing Research, 258(1), 134–42.

(p.307) Spence, C., Ranson, J., and Driver, J. (2000). Cross-modal selective attention: On the difficulty of ignoring sounds at the locus of visual attention. Perception and Psychophysics, 62, 410–24.

Sperber, D. and Wilson, D. (1986). Relevance: Communication and cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Sperling, G. (1960). The information available in brief visual presentations. Psychological Monographs: General and Applied, 74(11), 1–29.

Spratling, M. (2008). Predictive coding as a model of biased competition in visual attention. Vision Research, 48(12), 1391–408.

Sprigge, T. L. (1983). The vindication of absolute idealism. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

Starr, W. B. (under review). A preference semantics for imperatives.

Stazicker, J. (2011). Attention, visual consciousness and indeterminacy. Mind and Language, 26(2), 156–84.

Sterelny, K. (2003). Thought in a hostile world: The evolution of human cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.

Steward, H. (1997). The ontology of mind: Events, processes, and states. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Steward, H. (2012). Actions as processes. Philosophical Perspectives, 26(1), 373–88.

Steward, H. (2013). Processes, continuants, and individuals. Mind, 122(487), 781–812.

Stich, S. P. (1983). From folk psychology to cognitive science: The case against belief. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Stokes, D. (2013). Cognitive penetrability of perception. Philosophy Compass, 8(7), 646–63.

Stout, R. (1997). Processes. Philosophy, 72(279), 19–27.

Strawson, G. (1994). Mental reality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Strawson, G. (2003). Mental ballistics or the involuntariness of spontaneity. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 103(1), 227–56.

Styles, E. A. (1997). The psychology of attention. Oxford: Psychology Press.

Sundström, P. (1998). Consciousness and intentionality of action. 20th World Congress of Philosophy.

Sutherland, S. (1998). Feature selection. Nature, 392, 350.

Tang, Y. Y., Ma, Y., Wang, J., Fan, Y., Feng, S., Lu, Q., Yu, Q, Sui, D, Rothbart, M. K., Fan, M., and Posner, M. I. (2007). Short-term meditation training improves attention and self-regulation. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 104(43), 17152–6.

Taylor, B. (1977). Tense and continuity. Linguistics and Philosophy, 1(2), 199–220.

Taylor, B. (1985). Modes of occurrence. Oxford: Blackwell.

Taylor, J. (2013). Is attention necessary and sufficient for phenomenal consciousness? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 20(11–12), 173–94.

Teufel, C., Alexis, D. M., Todd, H., Lawrance-Owen, A. J., Clayton, N. S., and Davis, G. (2009). Social cognition modulates the sensory coding of observed gaze direction. Current Biology, 19(15), 1274–7.

Theeuwes, J. (2010). Top-down and bottom-up control of visual selection. Acta Psychologica, 135(2), 77–99.

Thomasson, A. (2000). After Brentano: A one-level theory of consciousness. European Journal of Philosophy, 8(2), 190–210.

Titchener, E. B. (1973 [1908]). Lectures on the elementary psychology of feeling and attention. Garden City, NY: Avery Publishing.

Tomasello, M. (2008). Origins of human communication. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Tomasello, M. (2014). A natural history of human thinking. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Tombu, M. and Jolicœur, P. (2004). Virtually no evidence for virtually perfect time-sharing. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 30(5), 795.

(p.308) Torralba, A., Oliva, A., Castelhano, M. S., and Henderson, J. M. (2006). Contextual guidance of eye movements and attention in real-world scenes: The role of global features in object search. Psychological Review, 113(4), 766–86.

Travis, C. S. (2004). The silence of the senses. Mind, 113(449), 57–94.

Treisman, A. (1964). Selective attention in man. British Medical Bulletin, 20(1), 12–16.

Treisman, A. (1969). Strategies and models of selective attention. Psychological Review, 76(3), 282–99.

Treisman, A. (1993). The perception of features and objects. In A. Baddeley and L. Weiskrantz (Eds), Attention: selection, awareness and control (pp. 5–35). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Treisman, A. (1998). Feature binding, attention and object perception. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences, 353(1373), 1295–306.

Treisman, A. (2006). How the deployment of attention determines what we see. Visual Cognition, 14(4–8), 411–43.

Treisman, A. and Gelade, G. (1980). A feature-integration theory of attention. Cognitive Psychology, 12, 97–136.

Treisman, A. and Paterson, R. (1984). Emergent features, attention, and object perception. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 10(1), 12–31.

Tsal, Y. and Shalev, L. (1996). Inattention magnifies perceived length: The attentional receptive field hypothesis. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 22(1), 233–43.

Tse, P. U. (2005). Voluntary attention modulates the brightness of overlapping transparent surfaces. Vision Research, 45, 1095–8.

Tse, P. U., Cavanagh, P., Intriligator, J., and Rivest, J. (1997). Attention distorts the perception of time. Investigative Ophthalmology and Visual Science, 38(4), S1151.

Tsotsos, J. K. (1990). Analyzing vision at the complexity level. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 13(3), 423–45.

Turatto, M., Mazza, V., and Umilta, C. (2005). Crossmodal object-based attention: Auditory objects affect visual processing. Cognition, 96(2), B55–B64.

Tye, M. (1995). Ten problems of consciousness: A representational theory of the phenomenal mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Tye, M. (1996). Orgasms again. Philosophical Issues, 7, 51–4.

Tye, M. (2000). Consciousness, color, and content. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Tye, M. (2002). Representationalism and the transparency of experience. Noûs, 36(1), 137–51.

Tye, M. (2003). Consciousness and persons: Unity and identity. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Tye, M. (2009). Consciousness revisited: Materialism without phenomenal concepts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Tye, M. (2010). Attention, seeing, and change blindness. Philosophical Issues, 20(1), 410–37.

Tye, M. and Wright, B. (2011). Is there a phenomenology of thought? In T. Bayne and M. Montague (Eds), Cognitive Phenomenology (pp. 326–44). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Valsecchi, M., Vescovi, M., and Turatto, M. (2010). Are the effects of attention on speed judgments genuinely perceptual? Attention, Perception, and Psychophysics, 72(3), 637–50.

Van der Heijden, A. H. (1992). Selective attention in vision. Oxford: Routledge.

Van Gulick, R. (2014). Consciousness. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring), Edward N. Zalta (Ed.), <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/consciousness/>.

Vecera, S. P. (2000). Toward a biased competition account of object-based segregation and attention. Brain and Mind, 1(3), 353–84.

Vecera, S. P., Flevaris, A. V., and Filapek, J. C. (2004). Exogenous spatial attention influences figure-ground assignment. Psychological Science, 15(1), 20–6.

Velleman, J. D. (1992). What happens when someone acts? Mind, 101(403), 461–81.

(p.309) Velmans, M. and Schneider, S. (Eds) (2008). The Blackwell companion to consciousness. Oxford: Wiley.

Vendler, Z. (1957). Verbs and times. Philosophical Review, 56, 143–60.

Wagatsuma, N., Shimizu, R., and Sakai, K. (2008). Spatial attention in early vision for the perception of border ownership. Journal of Vision, 8(7), 22.

Wagemans, J., Elder, J. H., Kubovy, M., Palmer, S. E., Peterson, M. A., Singh, M., and von der Heydt, R. (2012). A century of Gestalt psychology in visual perception: I. Perceptual grouping and figure-ground organization. Psychological Bulletin, 138(6), 1172–217.

Wallace, A. (2006). The attention revolution: Unlocking the power of the focused mind. Boston, MA: Wisdom.

Wallace, D. (2009). This is water: Some thoughts, delivered on a significant occasion about living a compassionate life. New York: Little, Brown.

Wang, K., Fan, J., Dong, Y., Wang, C., Lee, T., and Posner, M. I. (2005). Selective impairment of attentional networks of orienting and executive control in schizophrenia. Schizophrenia Research, 78(2–3), 235–41.

Watzl, S. (2010). The significance of attention. PhD dissertation, Columbia University.

Watzl, S. (2011a). Attention as structuring of the stream of consciousness. In C. Mole, D. Smithies, and W. Wu (Eds), Attention: Philosophical and psychological essays (pp. 145–73). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Watzl, S. (2011b). Review of “Attention Is Cognitive Unison” by Christopher Mole. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews, <https://ndpr.nd.edu/news/27026-attention-is-cognitive-unison-an-essay-in-philosophical-psychology>.

Watzl S. (2013). Silencing the experience of change. Philosophical Studies, 165(3), 1009–32.

Watzl S. (2014a). Attentional organization and the unity of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 21(7–8), 56–87.

Watzl S. (2014b). Perceptual guidance. Ratio, 27(4), 369–505.

Watzl, S. (forthcoming a). Is attention an object-directed attitude? In M. Montague and A. Grzankowski (Eds), Non-propositional intentionality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Watzl, S. (forthcoming b). Can intentionalism explain how attention affects appearances? In A. Pautz and D. Stoljar (Eds), Themes from Block. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Watzl, S. and Wu, W. (2012). Perplexities of consciousness, by Eric Schwitzgebel. Mind, 121(482), 524–9.

Wegner, D. M. (1994). Ironic processes of mental control. Psychological Review, 101(1), 34–52.

Wegner, D. M. (1997). Why the mind wanders. In J. D. Cohen and J. W. Schooler (Eds), Scientific approaches to consciousness (pp. 295–315). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

Weiskrantz, L. (1986). Blindsight: A case study and implications. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

White, A. R. (1963). Attending and noticing. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 63, 103–26.

White, A. R. (1964). Attention. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

Williams, B. (1973). Deciding to believe. In B. Williams, Problems of the Self (pp. 136–51). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Wilson, J. M. (1999). How superduper does a physicalist supervenience need to be? Philosophical Quarterly, 50(194), 33–52.

Wilson, J. M. (2013). A determinable-based account of metaphysical indeterminacy. Inquiry, 56(4), 359–85.

Winer, G. A. and Cottrell, J. E. (1996). Does anything leave the eye when we see? Extramission beliefs of children and adults. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 137–42.

Winer, G. A., Cottrell, J. E., Gregg, V., Fournier, J. S., and Bica, L. A. (2002). Fundamentally misunderstanding visual perception: Adults’ belief in visual emissions. American Psychologist, 57(6–7), 417.

(p.310) Wittgenstein, L. (1967). Zettel. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

Wolfe, J. M. (1994). Guided search 2.0: A revised model of visual search. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review, 1(2), 202–38.

Wolfe, J. M. and Horowitz, T. S. (2004). What attributes guide the deployment of visual attention and how do they do it? Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 5(6), 495–501.

Wolfe, J. M., Võ, M. L. H., Evans, K. K., and Greene, M. R. (2011). Visual search in scenes involves selective and nonselective pathways. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 15(2), 77–84.

Wolff, C. (1738). Psychologia empirica, prostat in Officina libraria Rengeriana.

Wolpert, D. M. (1997). Computational approaches to motor control. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 1(6), 209–16.

Wright, R. D. and Ward, L. M. (2008). Orienting of attention. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Wu, C. T., Weissman, D. H., Roberts, K. C., and Woldorff, M. G. (2007). The neural circuitry underlying the executive control of auditory spatial attention. Brain Research, 1134, 187–98.

Wu, W. (2011a). Confronting many-many problems: Attention and agentive control. Noûs, 45(1), 50–76.

Wu, W. (2011b). What is conscious attention? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 82(1), 93–120.

Wu, W. (2014). Attention. Oxford: Routledge.

Wundt, W. M. (1897). Outlines of psychology. New York: G. E. Stechert.

Yantis, S. (1993). Stimulus-driven attentional capture. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 2(5), 156–61.

Yantis, S. and Egeth, H. E. (1999). On the distinction between visual salience and stimulus-driven attentional capture. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 25(3), 661–76.

Yantis, S. and Jonides, J. (1990). Abrupt visual onsets and selective attention: Voluntary versus automatic allocation. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 16(1), 121–34.

Yarbus, A. L. (1967). Eye movements and vision. New York: Plenum Press.

Yeshurun, Y. and Carrasco, M. (1998). Attention improves or impairs visual performance by enhancing spatial resolution. Nature, 396, 72–5.

Yeshurun, Y. and Hein, E. (2011). Transient attention degrades perceived apparent motion. Perception, 40(8), 905–18.

Yeshurun, Y. and Levy, L. (2003). Transient spatial attention degrades temporal resolution. Psychological Science, 14(3), 225–31.

Yoshimi, J. (2004). Field theories of mind and brain. In L. Embree (Ed.), Gurwitsch’s relevancy for cognitive science (pp. 111–29). New York: Springer.

Zeimbekis, J. and Raftopoulos, A. (Eds) (2015). The Cognitive Penetrability of Perception: New Philosophical Perspectives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.